I've written some posts on the historical Jesus, although not recently. You can peruse them here (the link goes to my other blog, but many of them were cross-posted here) or you could look at my posts of interest and scroll down to "Historical Jesus" for the highlights reel. Enjoy.
Discuss this post at the Quodlibeta Forum
Sunday, March 27, 2016
Friday, March 04, 2016
Ethics and its importance to ancient Greek science
I noted in my previous blog post thatancient Greek science consisted of many different natural philosophies. In
fact, it’s wrong to speak of Greek science in the singular. I’ve also noted in
the past that if we judge Greek sciences by the standards of today (which,
despite the anachronism, many people do), it was not very effective at
generating true theories about the natural world. Finally, with few exceptions,
science in the ancient world had no technological or practical applications.
So, what was it for? That’s what I want to
explain in this post.
Each school of Greek philosophy, whether
Aristotelian, Platonic, Stoic or Epicurean, had a particular ethical system.
Philosophers of each school believed that their moral values were objectively
true: that’s to say they could use them to tell the difference between right
and wrong. For these Greeks, morality was not just a matter of opinion: it was
a rational issue with correct answers. Of course, the schools disagreed on what
the truth was, a point gleefully pointed out by the sceptics.
Consider for a moment what it means for there
to be objective moral values. It means that there is something about reality,
outside human minds, that makes those values true. J.D. Mackie used the analogy
of a game of chess. The rules of chess determine what is right and wrong in the
universe of a chessboard. Whatever happens in a chess match as pieces are moved
around, attack and defend, win or lose, ought to be consistent with the
external rules the game. For any move, you can analyse whether this is true –
you can get to ‘is’ from ‘ought’. Almost all philosophies of the past have
treated moral values in the same way. For any given action or thought, they
said, it is possible to determine through rational analysis whether it is
consistent with objective moral values.
So, like the rules of chess are for a
chessboard, objective moral values must be part of the rules that govern the
universe. In the owrds of Peter Harrison, ancient philosophers assumed that “a
moral order is built into the structure of the cosmos.”
For Platonists and Christians, the source
of these values is external to nature, that is the ideal Form of the good or
the nature of God respectively. Nonetheless, both Platonists and Christians
both assume that this external factor, be it the Form or God, is reflected in
physical reality. Their natural philosophies are intended to validate the
existence of the source of external moral values. That’s why Christian natural
philosophy is based on the universe as God’s creation, while Platonists
emphasized how the perfect Forms could be discerned in nature by philosophical
reflection.
Aristotelians held that the function of
humans was to live in line with virtue and that was the way to good living.
This functionalist approach is reflected in Aristotle’s natural philosophy as
well. He interpreted his famous observations of animals using this framework. His
theory of natural motion states that even matter strives to reach its proper
place and naturally moves towards it. To be happy, human beings must also
adhere to the path that nature has laid out for them.
The Stoics defined right living as being in
harmony with nature, which they deified through a form of pantheism. Because
they believed moral laws were built into the very structure of the universe,
Stoics had no trouble treating them as part of objective reality. The essential
point, though, is that the ethics of Stoicism informed their natural
philosophy, even though they might argue that it was nature that gave rise to
their ethics.
Epicureans emphasised human freedom and so
their natural philosophy demystified nature so that it provided a safe space
for human choice. In his On the Nature of
Things, Lucretius systematically runs through various phenomena to show how
the free man has nothing to fear from them. Indeed, Epicurus himself said that
once you understand a phenomenon sufficiently well to stop fearing it, you
don’t need to delve any further. In a way, this is the opposite approach to the
Stoics because the intention of Lucretius and Epicurus is to show that humans
are objectively free. Nonetheless, this is still an ethical maxim and one that
the Epicureans used to determine their natural philosophy. Once again, the
ethical maxims were prior to the natural philosophy which served them.
The primacy of ethics and the belief in
objective moral values explains both the multiplicity of Greek natural
philosophies and the differences between them. It also shows us how utterly
unlike modern science Greek natural philosophy was. Finally, it illustrates
that the Greek attitude towards science was identical to that of early and
medieval Christians. David Lindberg was fond of a metaphor he found in the work
of Roger Bacon – that natural philosophy was the handmaiden of Christian
theology. For the pagan Greek philosophers, whether they were theists or not,
science was the servant of ethics.
Discuss this post at the Quodlibeta Forum